(more smiles)
LPC wrote:The problem with the "word versus term schtick" is that it is incoherent and incomprehensible. Despite your desperate movements of your semantic walnut shells ("word" and "term"), and can still see the pea [sic], and I see no contradiction or inconsistency in what I have written.
I appreciate it when, without coaching, you admit your own incomprehension. Aside from the entertainment value it derives (which is why I (now) frequent this forum), you also give me an excuse to keep building my exposition of the law in greater detail.
The word "includes" has the same definition throughout the IRC: "The terms 'includes' and 'including' when used in a definition contained in this title shall not be deemed to exclude other things otherwise within the meaning of the term defined."
Since definitions explain the same thing in different words, we can infer the different words that can be substituted for "includes": they are basically "is defined as ... which shall not be deemed to exclude other things otherwise within the meaning of the term defined".
We can safely simplify: first, "is defined as" equals "means". Second, something not deemed to be excluded from a definition is thereby within the definition. Third, let's represent the term and the definition by X and Y. So "X includes Y" is the same as "X means Y and other things otherwise within the meaning of X".
Now whenever X is used in its own definition, there are two ways to interpret it. One is to use the dictionary definition ("D") of X. The other is to use the definition itself ("X") but in such a way as to avoid circularity. An example of the first is "X means all X's that are Y's", where the X in the definition is contextually demonstrated to be different from the X being defined, and the definition is (noncircularly) "all D's that are Y's". An example of the second is "X means all Y's, but not any X's which are Z's", where the definition of X is broken into two pieces (general definition, and specific exclusion), and X in the definition is contextually a placeholder equivalent to the X being (partially or fully) defined. This definition is (noncircularly) "all Y's that are not Z's".
(One might wonder why more words are spent in the second case if the simpler definition would suffice; the answer is that often Y and Z are so complex that the first formulation actually becomes easier to read and understand. I have not bothered to demonstrate the extant complex examples where this occurs.)
So, whenever X is used in its own definition, we must decide whether the context indicates the X in the definition is a different concept or the same concept as the X being defined.
Of course, since the original context in our case spoke of the "term defined", we could easily conclude the latter (X in definition is same as X being defined); but for the moment we are bypassing that obvious point. We could also argue as probative that the word "otherwise" automatically breaks the definition into parts and again concludes to the latter case ("otherwise" introduces the hypothetical that the definition could be otherwise than it is, a common legislative device); but I am waiving this point as well (solely for the sake of argument).
We are working with defining "X includes Y" as "X means Y and other things otherwise within the meaning of X". Obviously, if we chose the former option (X in definition is different from X being defined), we would simply revert to "X means Y or D". Then any clause of inclusion would automatically expand to the full dictionary definition D (e.g., the inclusion clauses of 3231(b)), which yields multiple contradictions when applied. This would be a third proof that X in definition is the same as X being defined.
But it is argued that when other things are already specified elsewhere in the meaning of X, they are the "other things" intended. Given a definition "E means A; E includes B" we substitute the definition of "includes" and get "E means A; (or) E means B; (or) E means other things besides B otherwise within the meaning of E". Well, since E includes B, the "other things" might well be just A; and this yields "E means A or B".
However, given another definition "E includes A; E includes B", we would get exactly the same result: "E means A; (or) E means other things besides A otherwise within the meaning of E; (or) E means B; (or) E means other things besides B otherwise within the meaning of E". Applying the previous logic, the "other things" not A are just B, and vice versa, and "E means A or B". (This would be a natural reading of 3401(c), but it rails against the hardened beliefs of some.)
We could, however, read "E includes A; E includes B" as meaning "E includes A and/or B", which then yields "E means A or B; (or) E means other things besides A and B otherwise within the meaning of E". (This would be the same case as if we found "E includes A" alone, with no other definition besides 7701(c).) Now we are left with no guidance as to the "other things" besides "the subject matter, the context, the legislative history, and the executive interpretation, i. e., the legislative environment" (Sims, 359 US 108). That is, we may look at the statutes, the code, the Congressional Record, the regulations, etc., but as for resort to a dictionary, that by omission would only be resorted to where the rest are silent.
We have the regulation in 26 CFR 403.5 which defines the "other things" as those of "same general class" (this regulation also appears in 27 CFR 27.11 and formerly 26 CFR 170.59; I have not rechecked these cites). We have the agreement of the 1st Circuit in Brigham that the "other things" are of "like kind and class" (quoting Neal v Clark, 95 US 704, which gave the canon that general terms should not expand past the "class of things enumerated"). And we have the singular example that no executive interpretation (e.g., regulations, IRS pronouncement) ever finds something within the full definition of an "including" term unless it finds it within one of the explicit clauses, not the implicit "other things" clause, thereby adding nothing to the USSC and regulations cited above.
So there is simply no support for reading "E includes A; E includes B" and interpreting "E means A or B or D". At best, the definition can only be expanded to "E means items in the class of A or B". Which is exactly Pete's position.